Author:
(1) David Staines.
4 Calvo Framework and 4.1 Household’s Problem
4.3 Household Equilibrium Conditions
4.5 Nominal Equilibrium Conditions
4.6 Real Equilibrium Conditions and 4.7 Shocks
5.2 Persistence and Policy Puzzles
6 Stochastic Equilibrium and 6.1 Ergodic Theory and Random Dynamical Systems
7 General Linearized Phillips Curve
8 Existence Results and 8.1 Main Results
9.2 Algebraic Aspects (I) Singularities and Covers
9.3 Algebraic Aspects (II) Homology
9.4 Algebraic Aspects (III) Schemes
9.5 Wider Economic Interpretations
10 Econometric and Theoretical Implications and 10.1 Identification and Trade-offs
10.4 Microeconomic Interpretation
Appendices
A Proof of Theorem 2 and A.1 Proof of Part (i)
B Proofs from Section 4 and B.1 Individual Product Demand (4.2)
B.2 Flexible Price Equilibrium and ZINSS (4.4)
B.4 Cost Minimization (4.6) and (10.4)
C Proofs from Section 5, and C.1 Puzzles, Policy and Persistence
D Stochastic Equilibrium and D.1 Non-Stochastic Equilibrium
D.2 Profits and Long-Run Growth
E Slopes and Eigenvalues and E.1 Slope Coefficients
E.4 Rouche’s Theorem Conditions
F Abstract Algebra and F.1 Homology Groups
F.4 Marginal Costs and Inflation
G Further Keynesian Models and G.1 Taylor Pricing
G.3 Unconventional Policy Settings
H Empirical Robustness and H.1 Parameter Selection
I Additional Evidence and I.1 Other Structural Parameters
I.3 Trend Inflation Volatility
This part begins by explaining the Lucas critique and its various interpretations. The second subsection sets out observational equivalences and relates them to the Lucas critique framework. This should be viewed as a failure of existing New Keynesian economics. I will go onto demonstrate that the approximation I construct "passes" this crucial aspect of the Lucas critique by breaking this equivalence. In Appendix C.2.3, I confirm that there are (correctly solved) multiple models of recent vintage that are still ensnared.
1. Mapping Micro to Macro
Lucas Jr [1976] heralded a new approach to macroeconomics that emphasised that models should be based on aggregation of the optimizing behaviour of agents. This methodology has become ubiquitous in modern research, providing an underlying motivation for all the New Keynesian models in this text. Researchers however have neglected to check solutions to DSGE models preserve the mapping from micro to macro. This paper analyses and exemplifies two threats to this connection. There are a priori reduced form approximations used in econometric work that do not represent neighboring stochastic systems because of failure to account for singularities. Principle 1 links this phenomenon back to the breakdown of constraints in individual optimization problems, akin to the common understanding of micro foundations. Secondly, there arise instances where the local approximation would be correct but ex post the dynamics of the reduced form are not consistent with the existence of nearby non-stochastic systems. In fact, these two forces combine to obscure any connection between the behavior of approximation solutions and the developments and mechanisms of an underlying non-linear New Keynesian economy.
2. Observational Equivalence
The sole formal contribution of Lucas Jr [1976] was to demonstrate the equivalence between a new classical Phillips curve and a then standard Keynesian formulation of the relationship. It is a seminal result of macroeconometrics. I am able to show that it still applies to popular New Keynesian formulations but breaks down when Calvo is solved correctly. It demonstrates a fundamental advantage of Keynesian over Classical monetary models.
3. Breakdown of Statistical Relationships
Lucas argued that statistical relationships like the Phillips curve[38] would break down when exploited for policy purposes.[39] This argument gained credence in the 1970s when there was stagflation (simultaneous increases in unemployment and inflation). The idea was central to the rise of New Classical economics, indeed it spurred the creation of DSGE. The result is only partially correct. He was right that the Phillips curve is not policy invariant, as the policy rule parameters affected the optimal supply decisions with drawbacks to monetary activism. He was also correct that there need not be an upward sloping relationship between inflation and output in equilibrium. On the other hand, this does not rule out systematic countercylical policy consistent with the Keynesian consensus (see Snowdon and Vane [2005]). Lastly, the comparative statics, part of Theorem 2, can be viewed as an analysis of policy regime changes of the kind considered by Lucas.
This part formalizes the traditional interpretation of the Lucas critique and proves that, subject to parametric conditions, it extends to the current benchmark solution of Calvo and the Rotemberg Phillips curves. The equivalence between these approximations is not novel, although the link back to Lucas is.
Proposition 11. (Lucas Critique) There can arise an observational equivalence between the Singular Calvo, Rotemberg and Lucas Phillips curves provided that ω > η.
Proof. Proposition 8 ensures the expectation terms vanish from the two forward-looking models. The rest of the proof is constructive. Equating (54) and (91) yields
which sets Rotemberg equal to Calvo. Deploying (81) and equating shows equivalence to the Lucas model when
the bound follows because these variances have to be strictly positive.
The interpretation is that provided the Phillips curve is sufficiently steep, then the methods of macro econometrics cannot be used to distinguish between these three underlying designs for the Phillips curve. As an empirical matter, this is doubtful. Empirical specifications of the Phillips curve strongly favor a flat slope (ω < 1), whilst micro econometric evidence strongly supports an inelastic labor supply (η > 1).[40] Furthermore, there appears to be greater volatility of monetary shocks relative to technology shocks than the model would support. These issues are taken up in detail, in Appendices H and I.
The broader interpretation is that these solutions are just barely "passing" the observational equivalence aspect of the Lucas critique. There are many dynamic variants of the Lucas model, featuring more sophisticated information frictions (see Angeletos et al. [2021] and Maćkowiak et al. [2023]). They typically generating flatter inflation-output trade-offs (Afrouzi and Yang [2021]). Thus with respect to these versions, forward-looking Phillips curves may still be ensnared by the critique. Conversely, by overturning the singular Calvo solution, I can rule out all these models too. We can do better than this.
The Divine Coincidence and lack of dynamics have helped motivate a move away from DSGE back to ad hoc models. With new methods and better results, I anticipate a reversal. Moreover, armed with corrected approximations to Calvo around ZINSS, it should be possible to search for similar observational equivalences, in a wider class of DSGE. The link with Taylor pricing, established in Section 10, is a starting point.
Author:
(1) David Staines.
This paper is available on arxiv under CC 4.0 license.
[38] He had in mind the original Phillips curve, a negative relationship between unemployment and inflation estimated by Phillips [1958].
[39] Similar ideas were advanced in the context of monetary targeting by Goodhart [1975] without formal mathematical underpinning. The principles are of wide application throughout economics.